Reb without a Cause: the antidote to absurdity
This is a story told to me by Jerry Shaffer:
A Rabbi,
doing marriage counseling, listened to the wife and said, "You are
right."
The
husband said, "Wait, listen to me," and after listening, the Rabbi
said, "You are right."
The
Rabbi's wife, listening behind the screen, said, "Rabbi, they can't both
be right!"
The Rabbi
replied, "You are right too."
And I don’t
mean this to apply only to marital disputes, or even just human relations. For
me it has become a guiding idea that all assertions of any kind (including 2 +
2 = 4) are both true and false. And this is equivalent to saying that x
(any assertion) and -x (the denial of that assertion) are both true.
Moreover, I also see this as
equivalent to there being no truth … if one conceives truth as something
which cannot be (truthfully) contradicted.[1] (But you see, here too
there could be a denial, since one might conceive truth differently, such that
there could be incompatible truths.) I try therefore to avoid use of the
term “true” or “truth” (and “false” etc.) and call my view the philosophy of
yes and no. Thus: If someone asks me a question to which they anticipate a
yes or no answer, I say, “yes and no.” And in each case the two
contradictories can be justified, or I prefer to say simply explained,
by reference to there being different senses of some key term or terms
within the question. Thus my stock example: Do unicorns exist? No, if by
“unicorn” you mean a horse with magical powers and a single horn on their
forehead. But Yes, if by “unicorn” you mean simply an animal with a
single horn on their forehead.
My claim is
that all yes-or-no questions have this dual kind of answer … even the
most apparently factual, even the most “obviously” moral, and so on. For
example:
Factual: Is Pluto a planet? No, if you accept the
current definition of “planet” decided on by the International Astronomical
Union. Yes, if you accept the definition of “planet” put forward by Alan
Stern, the principal investigator of the New Horizons probe to Pluto.[2]
Moral: Here I hesitate even to put down an example, even
though examples exist in abundance, since people tend to have heartfelt
convictions about them. Indeed, every major moral question is precisely a question
because it has strong advocates on both sides, all of whom consider their
opponents to be not just mistaken but downright stupid or even evil … if they
can be believed at all to hold such an absurd opinion! (Maybe Trumpers are just
kidding? Maybe Putin lovers are completely brainwashed? Maybe Nazi lovers
are just nuts? Maybe vegans are just fanatics? And so on without
limit.)
The
practical upshot for me of holding this philosophy has been to shake my head or
roll my eyes (if only my mental head or eyes) every time I hear someone make a
bald assertion as if disagreement were impossible,[3] or pose a question as if –
“of course” – there is an answer.
However,
please understand that my view also comes with a major proviso, which is that,
even for someone like myself who is shaking their head or rolling their eyes,
there can be and usually is a definite preference for one answer
over another. And I see these preferences as just as motivationally powerful as
the bald assertions … but without the gratuitous assumption that they contain
incontrovertible factuality on their side. Indeed, my strong hunch is that the
tail is wagging the dog when it comes to assertions: that is, it is not the
belief that something is true that makes us prefer that answer but rather our
preference for that answer that makes us believe it is true.[4]
To clarify: I am not suggesting
that if you would “prefer” to have a million dollars you will therefore believe
you have a million dollars. There are, I think, cases like that: belief
in God and the afterlife is an obvious example (that Dostoevsky makes much of
in The Brothers Karamazov precisely for this reason: that nothing but
“faith” could sustain such a belief). But more generally I have in mind the subjectivity
and psychology of belief. So for example, if you strongly believe that
two apples and two pears = four pieces of fruit, my suggestion is that an irresistible
feeling moves your mind to accept the conclusion. After all, someone might
argue that they could cut one of the apples in half so that you would have five
pieces of fruit. But this argument most likely would not move you to
change your opinion (unless they did in fact cut the apple in half, at which
point you might not know what to believe). Thus (i.e., that is the sense in
which) I am calling your belief a preference.[5]
And I see an advantage to my view in its clear-eyed modesty or metaphysical minimalism, since it seems to me that it is precisely the adamancy with which one clings to a claim or belief that causes most of the damage from having strong preferences. Thus, I see here the best of both worlds: One can have strong motivations without absurdity and fanaticism. Simply detach the former from the metaphysical nonsense of truth.
[1]
That last can be called analetheism (or just “letheism” without the double
negative).
[2]
Actually the dispute is more complex than this (and this too is a totally
common circumstance). For example, it can be and has certainly been argued that
even by the IAU’s new definition, Pluto still counts as a planet.
[3]
Indeed, assertions are conversation stoppers, and often intended as such.
(“It’s the right thing to do.” Case closed.) On the other hand (yes and no)
they can lead to endless debate. (“No it isn’t!”) This is why they are
antithetical to the attitude I prefer, which is one of forever trying to
understand rather than to “win.” (“Help me understand why you think, or what
you mean by saying, it’s right.”)
[4] This has its analogue in the moral
realm, where it implies a reversal of the presumed direction of moral dis/approval,
from dis/liking something because it is bad/good to judging something to be bad/good
because one dis/likes it. It is thus an empirical version of Socrates’ question
to Euthyphro about piety and the gods: “The point which I should first wish to understand is whether the pious
or holy is beloved by the gods because it is holy, or holy because it is
beloved of the gods.” The second disjunct -- pious (or impious) because
loved (or hated) by the gods -- is analogous to my position -- right (or
wrong) because liked (or disliked) by the moralist. Thus my position is at
odds with Socrates’ presumed preference for the first disjunct.
[5]
Another issue is whether it makes any sense to suppose you could even believe
something if you did not believe in truth … since what is belief if not the
belief that something is true? But this objection does not move me to
give up my position, since I have little doubt that there are alternative
conceptions of belief that do not rely on truth. For example, if you were to
ask someone who said they believed the Earth is round whether they thought it
was true that the Earth is round, I can easily imagine their replying,
“Truth is above my pay grade; all I know is that I believe it.”
Comments
Post a Comment